An Introduction to Environmental Ethics

An Introduction to Environmental Ethics

BY DAVID E.W. FENNER

Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee
Philosophers tend to divide the academic approach to ethics into two domains: theoretical ethics and practical/applied ethics. Environmental ethics is a practical/applied ethic; it is a system for determining correct action with regard to the natural world, either in specific situations or in terms of a general approach to the environment. "Environmental ethics as applied ethics," makes it sound as if environmental ethics is primarily or even exclusively the application of theoretical ethics-- the sorts of systems we get from the likes of Kant and Mill-- to environmental problems. This seems to be the wrong way to think about environmental ethics. It seems more functional and realistic to think about environmental ethics as the application of values. We start with our values, and then we see to what sorts of things those values committed us. When it comes to the natural world, there are a variety of positions that may describe an individual"s values. A good place to begin is with an exploration of what one holds to be of ultimate value. "Ultimate values," are "core values," values people hold that they would never relinquish and for which the question, "Why value that?" is virtually meaningless. For instance, if I were to hold human life as ultimately valuable -- what philosophers like to call "intrinsically" valuable -- then when asked, "Why do you value human life?" my answer can only be, "Because it"s valuable." Full stop. If I were to answer the question, "Because it allows me to experience the world," or, "It allows me to enjoy being with my family," or, "It allows me to explore my spirituality," then life is not my ultimate value. It is merely a means or an instrument that helps me reach something I value even more deeply (i.e., experience, family, or spirituality). So, a good place to begin to explore one"s environmental ethic is an exploration of one"s own ultimate, core, or intrinsic values. If one holds the entirety of the natural world as valuable -- valuable on its
Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee
own, without reference to human interests -- her position could be called "ecocentrist." Probably the most famous ecocentrist was Aldo Leopold. In his book, A Sand County Almanac, Leopold fashions the "Land Ethic." The "land" is his word for the entire ecosystem taken as a system. In the Land Ethic, the particular parts of the natural community are not unexpendable (the loss of one tree or one bird is not a problem). What is valued is the preservation of the entire natural system in balance, along with preservation of a healthy representation of all the members of that system. Leopold writes: All ethics so far evolved rest on a single premise: that the individual is a member of a community of interdependent parts... The land ethic simply enlarges the boundaries of the community to include soils, waters, plants, and animals, or collectively: the land... In short, a land ethic changes the role of Homo Sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain member and citizen of it.1
Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee
A modification of ecocentrism is "biocentrism," where the living elements of the natural world are seen as intrinsically valuable. On this view, biological entities-- plants and animals-- are considered intrinsically valuable. Biocentric approaches to environmental ethics include, but are not limited to, views that focus on animal rights. The nineteenth century philosopher Jeremy Bentham probably offered the first philosophical treatment of animal rights. Bentham writes, "The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?"2 Peter Singer, author of the famed Animal Liberation (Avon, 1991), writes:

Many philosophers have proposed the principle of equal consideration of interests, in some form or other, as a basic moral principle; but . . . not many of them have recognized that this principle applies to members of other species as well as to our own . . . Other animals have emotions and desires and appear to be capable of enjoying a good life... Surely every sentient being is capable of leading a life that is happier or less miserable than some alternative life, and hence has a claim to be taken into account. In this respect, the distinction between humans and nonhumans is not a sharp distinction, but rather a continuum along which we move gradually, and with overlaps between species, from simple capacities for enjoyment and satisfaction, or pain and suffering, to more complex ones.

There are many who see only the human species as having intrinsic value. This approach is broadly called, "anthropocentrism." The anthropocentrist holds that the natural world is merely instrumentally valuable and available to serve human interests. This is a popular approach. Perhaps it is so popular because it is the one most clearly advocated by mainline Christianity and the cultures in which Christianity plays so strong a role. The writer of Genesis says:
Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee
And God said, "Let us make man in our own image, after our likeness; and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth, and over every creeping thing that creepeth upon the earthÉand God said to them, Be fruitful, and multiply, and replenish the earth, and subdue it: and have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over every living thing that moveth upon the earth."4 Although this Biblical passage seems to give "man" a great deal of latitude, most Christians modestly prefer to interpret this passage as God giving humans a stewardship role over "creation." Humans are meant to use the earth and its resources for their own well-being; but they are also meant to care for it, so that it will continue to support human survival and flourishing. In a traditional anthropocentric view, one finds value to be in and about human interests. Humans have a clear and abiding interest in living in a healthy environmental context. We immediately value the air we breathe, the water we drink, and the food we eat. We also value the natural "resources" from which we make our livings, whether those natural elements are used directly by humans (as in the timber, petroleum or ore industries) or used indirectly (as in industries which use power generated by petroleum, etc.). It is our collective duty, then, to take care of our natural environment(s) in order to meet the needs and desires of humans.

There are, of course, other anthropocentric approaches. Some focus on the mental well-being that one can achieve through experiences in nature; some focus on the beauty of the natural world; others focus more narrowly on the individual self.

Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee

Those views that focus on the individual self are called "egocentric." Here, one finds value to be in and about proximal human interests. By "proximal," I mean, "close." Some theorists object that humans do not necessarily care about what happens to other humans on the other side of the planet, but they do care about what happens to them. Is this a "selfish" ethic? It depends on how you look at it. Suppose one is concerned with oneself, with his or her own interests, survival and flourishing. Wouldn't that individual also be concerned with the interests of his or her spouse? Children? Grandchildren? Friends? Relatives? Neighbors? Colleagues? "Pets?" One who has "proximal" values has values regarding those with whom one finds oneself in relation. It is, on this view, each person's duty to take care of the natural environment, of him/herself and all those with whom s/he has a relationship; this could translate into one taking care of his or her neighborhood, community, town or even state or nation. We usually call this, "Enlightened Self-Interest." The key to understanding this ethic is to understand properly the scope or range of "self-interest." Above was noted that the scope of self-interest includes all those others (even some non-human animals) who are in relationship with the person in question. But it is equally important to note that the scope of self-interest also extends in time: I am not just concerned with my present interests, but in my future ones as well; I am not just concerned with my children's interests, but with my (potential) grandchildren's interests, too.

In terms of environmental ethics, the "least common denominator" is the last in the above list. People can be regularly counted on to do what is in their own interests. This does not mean they are unethical or even that they are selfish. They just have a simple system of ethics that starts with what they most immediately, and in fact, value.
Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee

If this sort of ethic is one we can expect every human being to share, how is it, then, that human beings can fail to do the right thing? If environmental-ethical motivations are a matter of human nature, why do we find unethical acts being committed against the natural world? It is too often the case that people do not do the right thing -- even when it is explicitly in their own interests to do so -- because they "cannot see the forest for the trees." They focus on short-term goals rather than on long-term goals. If one's goal is to put food on the table, then the healthfulness of the food and the cleanness of the drink that ends up on that table may be ignored or suppressed as a goal, so that one can focus on the goal of building that off-shore oil rig, the completion of which means that he can keep his job. The short-term goal of maintaining a job with a good salary, so that one can put food on the table, may overwhelm the long-term goal of engaging only in those actions that contribute to the food on the table being edible and safe. I do not want to say this is the only explanation to the problem of how people seem to defy their own best interests, but I think it is an explanation which focuses on a very common phenomenon today: not seeing the forest for the trees.

The good news is that (almost) everyone has an environmental ethic. It
Shaun Snee
Photo ©Shaun Snee
may not be one that is highly systematized or even very considered; but, except for pathologically antisocial individuals, everyone holds some values that concern her interaction with the natural world. Apparently, everyone starts with the "least common denominator" view mentioned above. But many move beyond this view and take on a higher, less anthropocentric, ethic by finding value outside just the human self. Change or growth, though, must be internal and self-motivated. The move from the "least common denominator" view to a larger environmental ethic can be encouraged by providing opportunities designed to foster or serve as a context for individual growth. "Moralizing" and "proselytizing" will not work, but facilitation and guidance will. The key is experience -- and, of course, appreciation of the experience of the natural world. It is through such experience that we will grow as environmentally ethical persons.

REFERENCES

Leopold, A. A Sand County Almanac (Oxford University Press, 1949), pp. 203-204.

Bentham, J. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Ch. XVII (1789). Singer, P. "All Animals are Equal" in T. Regan and P. Singer, eds., Animal Rights and Human Obligations, second edition (Prentice Hall, 1989), pp. 78 and 82. This essay first appeared in Philosophical Exchange I (5), 1976.

Genesis, Chapter 1, Verses 26-28, King James Version.

 

Copyright ©2004 Global Underwater Explorers.
All rights reserved.